Photo AI
Last Updated Sep 26, 2025
Revision notes with simplified explanations to understand The problem of evil and suffering quickly and effectively.
364+ students studying
The problem of evil is a longstanding dilemma in the philosophy of religion, originating in ancient Greece with Epicurus, who first articulated the logical challenge of believing in an all-loving and all-powerful God in the presence of evil. It presents a profound challenge to traditional monotheism. If God exists, why doesn't he prevent these atrocities?
💡 Theists have developed various theodicies (derived from the Greek words "theos" for God and "dikē" for justice, meaning "justifying God") to address this issue.
The logical problem of evil: is an a priori, deductive argument that proposes that it is a logical contradiction for evil, an omnipotent and omnibenevolent God to logically exist.
Epicurus: an ancient Greek philosopher who laid the foundations of the logical problem of evil. Epicurus claimed that the proposition that God is omnipotent, and omnibenevolent is inconsistent with the idea of evil existing. however, his original works have never been found, so we know of his argument through the writings of empiricist Hume. David Hume: Hume concludes that to accept evil exists means accepting that "God is either impotent or malicious", which means the nature of God presented by the God of classical theism is wrong and therefore cannot possibly exist.
J.L. Mackie: Mackie's aim is to show that philosophy is not only capable of criticizing arguments for God's existence but also of showing that God does not exist, thus closing off the position. Mackie refers to what is known as the 'inconsistent triad' – in other words, the inconsistency between the three ideas of:
From the three ideas within the problem of evil, only two of them can be true.
As evil – both moral and natural – is clearly a feature of this world, either God is not omnipotent (i.e. He cannot stop evil), or God is not omnibenevolent (i.e. He does not love us or care about us (and other living creatures that can feel pain) enough to stop evil. As Mackie says, though, these three are not formally contradictory. To show that they are inconsistent, we have to add some further principles.
Mackie gives us two:
Adequate solution: Mackie agrees that the problem for the theologian can be solved by giving up one of the three principles with which we began: we can deny that God is omnipotent or all good, or we can deny that there is any evil in the world.
Alfred North Whitehead: argues that God is a changeable God who improves over time. God is not omnipotent or morally perfect and so could not create a perfect universe, this explains natural evil. Similarly, he could not create perfect humans - just humans with the potential for perfection; this explains moral evil. The 'divine lure' of God lures us to be better people, but, he cannot force us. The problem with this solution is that Mackie thinks that most theists will be unwilling to take this approach, for doing so leaves them with a conception of a God that isn't worthy of worship - and therefore not religiously significant. Therefore, although these solutions are 'adequate', they are not really successful. Fallacious solutions: Fallacious solutions are solutions which, even though they may seem plausible at first, in fact, do not amount to the rejection of any principle that gave rise to the contradiction, thus they commit logical fallacies. Good cannot exist without evil, since evil is necessary as a counterpart to good. The basic idea here is that God could not have made a world that had any good without allowing some evil, since it is impossible for goodness to exist without evil.
For Mackie, no amount of evil is justifiable for a benevolent and omnipotent God.
The basic idea here is that certain kinds of evil are necessary for certain kinds of good; e.g. without disease and pain, it would be logically impossible to have medical advances and feelings of sympathy. Evil is necessary for free will: Mackie argues that many kinds of evil are not the result of God's actions but of the free actions of human beings. Mackie's main objection is this 'If God has made men such that in their free choices they sometimes prefer what is good and sometimes what is evil, why could he not have made men such that they always freely choose the good?', is it because he could not? If not it is because he is not the omnipotent.
He points out that a "wholly good being eliminated evil as far as it can be." This means that the God of Classical Theism cannot exist as it is logically impossible. Mackie claims that if God existed, he would eliminate evil – but this isn't the case, therefore God can't exist.
Therefore, Mackie argues that the theodicies do not give a solution to the problem of evil since they have changed the premise (i.e. that God is omnipotent).
Mackie claims that the only solution to the logical problem is to deny this and that all so called 'solutions' or 'theodicies' actually limit God's power but misleadingly keep the term 'omnipotence'. He argues "...the theologian can, if he wishes, accept this criticism. He can admit that no rational proof of God's existence is possible and, he can still retain all that is essential to his position, by holding that God's existence is known in some other, non-rational way." In this Mackie notes that this need not convince someone that there is no reason for believing in God (reminiscent of Flews 'death by thousand qualification argument), but that they have to accept that all the arguments for God's existence have been shown by philosophers to be faulty.
The evidential problem of evil is an a posteriori, inductive argument that takes it's argument from the evidence our senses provide leading to the most probable conclusion. In essence, it proposes that this world demonstrates enough evidence to argue that the monotheist God probably does not exist.
In his book 'Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion', Hume crafts a conversation between three philosophers who debate the nature of God's existence. In the wake of Philo's attack on the a priori arguments for God's existence, Demea, the most orthodox of the three characters, rather unguardedly proposes that the source of religious faith is the misery of human existence. Awareness of his own misery, he suggests, leads man to seek protection from that Being on whom he and all nature are dependent (God). It is here that that Hume brings his argument to life stating 'The whole earth ... is cursed and polluted. A perpetual war is kindled amongst all living creatures. Necessity, hunger, want stimulate the strong and the courageous: fear, anxiety, terror agitate the weak and the infirm. The first entrance into life gives anguish to the new-born infant and to its wretched parent: weakness, impotence, distress attend each stage of that life, and it is, at last, finished in agony and horror.' Indicating that suffering is exists in the world for all creatures: humans and animals. Hume is being hyperbolic, where he is trying to indicate the obvious flaw in this world caused by evident suffering which flies in the face of the nature of the God of classical theism.
J.S. Mill argued that the presence of evil within the natural world offers a rational basis to conclude that it isn't necessary to infer that a being of infinite goodness is at the root of their cause. He writes: 'in sober truth, nearly all the things which men are hanged or imprisoned for doing to one another are nature's everyday'. From this point we can argue that those who try to prove the existence of God a posteriori are mistaken in thinking that evidence points to an omnibenevolent creator and if it points to any creator at all, it is one who is sadistic and behaves in ways that we would punish from human criminals.
Rowe, modern day philosopher, wrote a paper on entitled 'The Problem of Evil and Some Varieties of Atheism' (1979) in which he highlighted that the evidence in the world around us shows us that there is a clear argument for atheism. Rowe focuses predominately on the intensity of moral and natural suffering and evil that we are able to observe in the world that happens regularly.
Rowe rationalises 'The argument is valid; therefore, if we have rational grounds for accepting its premises, to that extent we have rational grounds for accepting atheism.' He propounds his argument by stating that 'intense human and animal suffering as this occurs on a daily basis, is in great plenitude in our world, and is a clear case of evil. More precisely, it is a case of intrinsic evil: it is bad in and of itself, even though it sometimes is part of, or leads to, some good state of affairs.' Rowe accepts that if this evil and suffering resulted in some greater good, then it may have a purpose, however, this argument is negated by the fact that the type of suffering and intensity of suffering prevalent in the world.
Rowe gives an example in the case of a suffering Fawn, where by he describes the following, (sometimes referred to as the case of Bambi): In some distant forest lighting strikes a dead tree, resulting in a forest fire. In the fire a fawn is trapped, horribly burned, and he's in terrible agony for several days before death relives the suffering. In light of his example Rowe asks the following question, "Is it reasonable to believe that there is some greater good so intimately connected to that suffering that even an omnipotent, omniscient being could not have obtained that good without permitting that suffering or some evil at least as bad? Rowe is drawing our attention to the fact that through there may be a need for suffering surely a loving god would have ended the pointless suffering present in this story, which quite easily could be true.
Bruce Russell 1989 supported Rowes argument using a story from an article he read on the train, refer to as the case of Sue: The girl's mother was living with her boyfriend, another man who was unemployed, her two children, and her 9-month old infant fathered by the boyfriend. On New Year's Eve all three adults were drinking at a bar near the woman's home. The boyfriend had been taking drugs and drinking heavily. He was asked to leave the bar at 8:00 p.m. After several reappearances he finally stayed away for good at about 9:30 p.m. The woman and the unemployed man remained at the bar until 2:00 a.m. at which time the woman went home and the man to a party at a neighbour's home. Perhaps out of jealousy, the boyfriend attacked the woman when she walked into the house. Her brother was there and broke up the fight by hitting the boyfriend who was passed out and slumped over a table when the brother left. Later the boyfriend attacked the woman again, and this time she knocked him unconscious. After checking the children, she went to bed. Later the woman's 5-year old girl went downstairs to go to the bathroom. The unemployed man returned from the party at 3:45 a.m. and found the 5-year old dead. She had been raped, severely beaten over most of her body and strangled to death by the boyfriend. Rowe's contention with these examples is that the 5-year-old did not need to be raped and severely beaten before she was murdered, if it was her death that needed to take place to bring about the greater good. Ultimately, Rowe is arguing that the evidence for unnecessary evil points to the non- existence of the God of monotheism.
Gregory Paul agrees with Rowe and argues that the death of so many innocent children challenges the existence of God. He estimates that over 50 billion children have died naturally and some 300 billion human beings have died naturally but prenatally. He argues: • Millions of innocent children suffer and die every year, from both natural and evil causes. • These children are too young to be able to make choices about God – they have no freewill. • No all-loving, all-powerful being would permit such suffering. • Therefore, God does not exist
Enhance your understanding with flashcards, quizzes, and exams—designed to help you grasp key concepts, reinforce learning, and master any topic with confidence!
30 flashcards
Flashcards on The problem of evil and suffering
Revise key concepts with interactive flashcards.
Try Religious Studies Flashcards3 quizzes
Quizzes on The problem of evil and suffering
Test your knowledge with fun and engaging quizzes.
Try Religious Studies Quizzes29 questions
Exam questions on The problem of evil and suffering
Boost your confidence with real exam questions.
Try Religious Studies Questions27 exams created
Exam Builder on The problem of evil and suffering
Create custom exams across topics for better practice!
Try Religious Studies exam builder25 papers
Past Papers on The problem of evil and suffering
Practice past papers to reinforce exam experience.
Try Religious Studies Past PapersDiscover More Revision Notes Related to The problem of evil and suffering to Deepen Your Understanding and Improve Your Mastery
96%
114 rated
The problem of evil
Theodicies that justify divine action or inaction in the face of evil
286+ studying
185KViewsJoin 500,000+ A-Level students using SimpleStudy...
Join Thousands of A-Level Students Using SimpleStudy to Learn Smarter, Stay Organized, and Boost Their Grades with Confidence!
Report Improved Results
Recommend to friends
Students Supported
Questions answered